Visions of inequality

In this next of a series of reviews of some important books published this year, I look at Branco Milanovic’s Visions of Inequality.

Branco Milanovic, former senior economist at the World Bank, has written yet another intriguing book on global inequality.  Over the years, Milanovic has established his reputation as the expert on global inequality through papers and books that accumulate detailed and revealing statistics on the inequality of wealth and income within nations, between nations; and between rich individuals in the West and poor people in the periphery; also showing the changing trends in inequality over the last century or more.

But Visions of Inequality takes a different approach from the stats.  Milanovic identifies those authors that he considers have the most important explanations of why inequality of wealth and income is so great between humans.  As Milanovic puts it: “The objective of this book is to trace the evolution of thinking about economic inequality over the past two centuries, based on the works of some influential economists whose writings can be interpreted to deal, directly or indirectly, with income distribution and income inequality. They are François Quesnay, Adam Smith, David Ricardo, Karl Marx, Vilfredo Pareto, Simon Kuznets, and a group of economists from the second half of the twentieth century (the latter collectively influential even as they individually lack the iconic status of the prior six).” The latter includes Thomas Piketty.

Before we consider Milanovic’s discussion of these economists views on inequality, let us remind ourselves of just how unequal the world is in terms of wealth in 2023.

And in the richest large country in the world, the latest data show that the top 0.01% of American households have 5.5% of all personal wealth; the top 0.01% have 14.7%, the top 1% have staggering 35.1% and the top 10% have 73.4%, according to the latest Fed survey on consumer finances. 

It is not possible to go through all the ‘visions’ of inequality described by Milanovic, so unsurprisingly, I shall concentrate on Milanovic’s analysis of Marx on inequality. Milanovic reckons that Marx’s “theory of value can be treated entirely distinctly (that is, left out) from the discussion of forces that, according to Marx, affect income distribution between classes.”  That is an interesting observation that I am not sure is correct – as I shall attempt to explain below.

Milanovic goes on that “it should be noted that Marx was generally uninterested in questions of inequality in the way that we pose them now. His view, shared by most Marxists, was that unless the background institutions of capitalism—namely, private ownership of means of production and hired labor— were swept away, any political struggles to reduce inequality could at best lead to reformism, trade unionism, and what Lenin later called “opportunism.” Inequality was thus a derivative, secondary issue, barely addressed in Marx’s writings.”

Again, I am not sure that it is correct that Marx was not interested in inequality, although Milanovic correctly identifies that Marx saw inequality and poverty under capitalism as the result of the private ownership of the means of production and the exploitation of labour power, not due to regressive taxation, low wages or monopoly, as such.  Milanovic points out that “descriptions of poverty and inequality fill the pages of Capital, especially its first volume. But they are there to show the reality of capitalist society and the need to end the system of wage-labor. They are not there to advocate reductions of inequality and poverty within the existing system.”

Milanovic makes the currently usual view that Marx’s view of capitalism and thus inequality was ‘unfinished’.  He accepts that “some important parts (like the discussion of the tendency of the profit rate to fall) are clearly unfinished.”  For Milanovic, Marx wrote in a chaotic way, but even so there were “true diamonds in the rough”.  And Marx was no dry theorist.  Despite the dearth of empirical data in the mid-19th century, he diligently tried to dig up evidence to back his vision of capitalism. “Marx’s use of data and facts marked a dramatic improvement upon Ricardo and Smith. Pareto would take this to a new level because of his access to the fiscal data on income distribution. …Marx, too, cited fiscal data on English and Irish income distributions—the same type of data that three decades later would provide the empirical core of Pareto’s claims.”

Milanovic provides the reader with an interesting review of Marx’s own place in the distribution of wealth.  He was born into the top 5% tier of households in Trier, now in west Germany.  Of course, as it panned out for Marx and his family in their refugee travels across Europe to England, that wealthy start was not to be sustained during his life – at least not until near the end.

Milanovic reveals just how wealth inequality in the UK increased throughout most of the eighteenth and nineteenth centuries before peaking just on the eve of the First World War. At the time that Marx was writing Capital, wealth inequality in the UK was not only rising but exceptionally high: the top one percent of wealth-holders owned around 60 percent of the country’s wealth. As the data above shows, the top 1% in the US now have about 35%.

Income inequality was very high too and most likely increasing until around the 1870s. At the time of Adam Smith’s The Wealth of Nations (1776), the average income of capitalists was eleven times and that of landlords thirty-three times greater than the average income of workers. At the time of Capital—about a century later— the workers’ position was even worse vis-à-vis the capitalists (who now made fifteen times more).

Back in the 1840s, Engels wrote about the low real wages experienced by labour during the industrial revolution in his seminal work, the Condition of the Working Class in England (1845).  But after what has been called ‘Engel’s pause’, real wages started to rise, partly due to workers obtaining a share of increased productivity of labour, but also from transfers of profits from the huge colonial empires that England had accrued by the mid-19th century.

But Marx noted that there was “simultaneously an increase in the real wage and a declining labor share.” This, I will argue below, is key to Marx’s view on inequality.  Milanovic explains that Marx considered that any distribution of the means of consumption was only a consequence of the distribution of the conditions of production. And the latter was a feature of the mode of production. The capitalist mode of production rests on the fact that the material conditions of production are in the hands of non-workers in the form of property in capital and land, while the masses are only owners of their personal condition of production, of labor power. Thus, the distribution of income and wealth cannot be changed in any material way until the system is changed. The issue is the abolition of classes, not marginal alteration of income inequality.  “To clamor for equal or even equitable remuneration on the basis of the wages system,” Marx writes, “is the same as to clamor for freedom on the basis of the slavery system.”

This is where I find it strange for Milanovic to claim (as above) that Marx’s theory of value has no connection to his explanation of inequality.  Indeed, Milanovic says that Marx’s theory of exploitation is of commodity “exchange that is based fully on the law of value: the workers are not treated unfairly, nor are they paid less than the value of their labor-power. Exploitation comes from this specific feature of labor: its ability to produce value greater than the value of goods and services expended in that effort and therefore necessary to compensate it. From the theory of exploitation comes also the conclusion that profit is the surplus value in another guise.”

From Marx’s value theory, we can derive a theory of classes in capitalist society.  And Milanovic outlines its features from Marx’s works.

Also, what flows from Marx’s value theory is that wage differences among countries are generated by the rise in the technical composition of capital and productivity differentials. Milanovic: “the more productive is one country relative to another in the world market, the higher will be its wages, compared to another.”  In a note in Capital volume III, Marx shows the difference in the nominal wages between the UK, France, Prussia, Austria, and Russia.

The ratio of nominal wages in the UK is at the top, with Russia at the bottom, at 5 to 1, matching the pecking order in technical development.

Marx argues that the very concept of what is the minimal acceptable wage is historical;  “indeed, it would be hard to imagine Marx, for whom all economic categories are historical, not applying the same logic to labor-power.” (Milanovic).  As Marx says in volume III of Capital: “The actual value of labour-power diverges from the physical minimum; it differs according to climate and the level of social development; it depends not only on the physical needs but also on historically-developed social needs.”  I think this observation is important in the debate about whether the exploitation of the Global South by the rich imperialist bloc is mainly due to very low wages in the former rather than mainly due to the productive power of the imperialist bloc to grab the lion’s share of profit through international trade and investment.

Marx looked for empirical evidence on inequality of income in his time.  In Volume One of Capital, he illustrates inequality using the 1865 income tax data from England and Wales.  Indeed, Milanovic makes the interesting observation that if Marx had transformed the tax data that he shows in Capital in the same way that Pareto would soon do, he would have obtained a graph showing a Pareto coefficient of 1.2, which is implies a very thick right-end tail of income distribution or a very high ‘Gini coefficient’ (in modern terms).

On inequality, Milanovic refers to Marx’s view that it is a relative concept: A house may be large or small; as long as the neighboring houses are likewise small, it satisfies all social requirement for a residence. But let there arise next to the little house a palace, and the little house shrinks to a hut. The little house now makes it clear that its inmate has no social position at all to maintain, or but a very insignificant one.” 

And on needs, Marx explains: Our wants and pleasures have their origin in society; we therefore measure them in relation to society; we do not measure them in relation to the objects which serve for their gratification. Since they are of a social nature, they are of a relative nature.”  Most Americans are rich in income or wealth compared to those living in sub-Saharan Africa or India, but that is not the benchmark for Americans – the benchmark is their wealth and income compared to those ruling their country.

Milanovic takes us through Marx’s law of the tendency of the rate of profit to fall in a broadly accurate manner.  However, he accepts the distortion of that law propounded by Michael Heinrich and others that the law is ‘indeterminate’“Heinrich is right to state that the increase in s / v is not a force that counteracts the law”.  But Milanovic ‘saves’ the law with various arguments that a rising rate of surplus value will not sufficiently counteract a rising organic composition of capital and “We are thus back to Marx’s original, and crucial, contention that the profit rate will decline with greater capital intensity of production unless the effect of that change is offset by greater exploitation of labor.

Milanovic picks up a point that many Marxists miss about the law, namely that it is both the explanation of regular and recurring cycles of crises (booms and slumps) and also a secular law indicating the ultimate failure of capitalist production to develop the productive forces for humanity.  “It is the joint or rather simultaneous action of the two—the coincidence of the secular low profits and economic crises—that will spell the end of capitalism.

Milanovic goes into a detailed account of the counteracting forces that deter or slow the fall in the rate profit to be found in Volume 3 of Capital chapter 14.  Then he reaches this conclusion.  “The tendency of the profit rate to fall must reduce inequality because capitalists (together with landlords who are treated just as a subgroup of capitalists) are the richest class. Clearly, if the top class’s incomes do not rise, or even decline, we may expect an improvement in distribution. This may be true even if there is an increased concentration of capitalists’ incomes and some capitalists become very rich while others go bankrupt and join workers.”

And he presents us with four possible income distributions from Marx’s law of profitability.

These are based on his assertion that a falling rate of profit will mean reduced inequality because real wages rise.  But this does not work for me.  I think it confuses the rate of surplus value with the rate of profit.  Milanovic’s four possibilities arise from his acceptance that Marx’s law is indeterminate and that it is the rate of profit that decides changes in inequality, not the rate of exploitation. Inequality can rise when the rate of profit is falling because the rate of surplus value and the mass of profit are rising.  A rising s/v can mean more s for an ever smaller group of capitalists and a rising v for an ever greater group of workers.

Take the major capitalist economies in the post-war period.  Inequality of income and wealth was relatively stable in the Golden Age of 1946-64 when the rate of profit was high and even rising.  Inequality rose sharply from the 1980s to the end of the 20th century when the rate of profit was rising mainly due to a rising rate of surplus value a la Milanovic. 

But since 2000, the rate of profit has stagnated or fallen but inequality continued to rise along with a rising rate of surplus value – as Milanovic himself shows. 

Milanovic also claims that the development of ‘homoploutia’, the supposed trend among the richest income groups to be both labor-income and capital-income rich “by receiving high wages in return for their high-skill labor as well as profits from their ownership of assets” weakens Marx’s theory of exploitation.  I don’t think so, particularly as there is strong evidence that the top earners still get their income from capital rather than wages.

The idea that a rising rate of profit is necessary to increase inequality is not Marx’s, but that of Thomas Piketty, in his acclaimed book, Capital in the 21st century.   Indeed, as Milanovic contrasts Piketty’s theory of inequality with that of Marx. “Piketty has thus proposed an entirely new and compelling argument that peaceful development of capitalism leads to the breakdown of the system—not because the profit rate crashes to zero and capitalists give up investing (as Marx would have it), but for the very opposite reason that capitalists tend to end up in possession of a society’s entire output and that is a socially unsustainable situation. In Marx’s view, capitalists (as a class) fail because they are not too successful; in Piketty’s view, they fail because they are too successful.”

To sum up, Milanovic says that “we have on offer three theories of income distribution in capitalism. First, there is Marx’s theory, by which increasing concentration of ownership of capital and decreasing rate of profit ultimately lead to the death of capitalism through zero investments. Second, we have Kuznets’s hypothesis of a wave of rising and then decreasing inequality— or as I have argued, successive waves.  And third, now, there is Piketty’s theory of unfettered capitalism that, left to its own devices, maintains an unchanged rate of return and sees the top earners’ share of capital income increasing to the point that it threatens to swallow the entire output of the society, and only a political response can prevent such an outcome.”

Given Marx’s compelling explanation of inequality of income and wealth derived from his theory of value and exploitation, Milanovic asks “why do we tend to ignore his views on equality? The answer, I suspect, is that after the cataclysmic failures of socialism and ideological ascendance of neoliberal ideology, we have tacitly accepted the permanence of capitalism. If one has such a view, then indeed it makes sense to refashion Marx as a pro-equality thinker who cared about trade union activity, equal opportunity, higher workers’ wages and the like. In other words, if we have given up on the idea of ending capitalism, we can try to repurpose Marx into the apostle of equality under capitalism. But it may not be easy. After all, if the Left tosses out the idea of transcending capitalism, can it be said to be Left-wing at all?”

Indeed.  But I would remind the reader of what Milanovic concluded in another book of his, Capitalism Alone.  “Capitalism gets much wrong, but also much right—and it is not going anywhere. Our task is to improve it.” Milanovic does not like capitalism and its inequalities, but to use Margaret Thatcher’s phrase in referring to her neoliberal policies for capitalism: he reckons there is no alternative (TINA).  So the aim must be, just as Keynes argued in the 1930s: “to make capitalism more sustainable. And that’s exactly what I think we should do now”.

That’s not Marx’s vision of inequality and how to end it. I put it this way in another paper:Policies aimed at reducing inequality of income by taxation and regulation, or even by boosting workers’ wages, will not achieve much impact while there is such a high level of inequality of wealth. And when that inequality of wealth stems from the concentration of the means of production and finance in the hands of a few.

25 thoughts on “Visions of inequality

  1. Milanovic is wrong when he claims the TPRF should reduce inequality because according to the theory OCC has to rise even if secularly.

    Since OCC, by definition, means wealth in dead labor — which is definitionally in the hands of the capitalist class — rises relative to living labor (definitionally, the property of the working class), inequality must always rise with the TPRF.

    When OCC rises, the value required to become a member of the capitalist class rises, thus making upward social mobility increasingly harder and downward social mobility increasingly easier. Then comes a turning point, where the sum of all variable capital and hoarded wealth becomes absolutely lower than total fixed capital, a point in which even if every member of the working class united their salaries, they wouldn’t be able to be the owners of the means of production. At this theoretical point, capitalism’s upwards social mobility ceases entirely and downwards social mobility accelerates to its maximum possible speed. Reform a la social-democracy also becomes absolutely impossible, because the Welfare State* and the Armed Forces also have, in capitalism, an OCC, and, given they are forbidden to have a positive profit rate, their OCC will always fall relatively (the Armed Forces will avoid that because it is a capitalist class’ consortium overseen by the State).

    The “eureka” moment here lies in the fact that such inequality can only be observed with 100% precision between the two essential classes of capitalism: the capitalist and the proletarian; and only on a universal scale, not on a nation-state scale (e.g. of course that inequality in a micro nation such as Luxembourg or Switzerland may fall, but they are not THE capitalist system, only a fragment of it).

    Another empirical diffculty is that we’re already living in an era of transition from capitalism to socialism, so it is hard, if not impossible, to measure with 100% precision the gravitational pull of the TPRF on inequality. For example, most of the industrial proletariat is in a socialist country, China, so they are insulated to an extent from TPRF inequality. We may never be able to measure it because of the newborn socialism’s effect on capitalism’s OCC (unless the American Empire manages to defeat China in WWIII, thus repeating its success against the USSR).

    *Even if, somehow, some country managed to create a for profit Welfare State, that would mean the working class would be fleeced anyway, as it would behave like any other individual capital. This profit cannot come from the capitalist class because to profit from the capitalist class is merely to transfer already created value. That’s why the capitalist class frequently say that to profit from them is “stealing”: of course, the entire point of capitalism is to serve the capitalist class (and, dialectically, vice versa), the clue is in the name.

    1. “For example, most of the industrial proletariat is in a socialist country, China, so they are insulated to an extent from TPRF inequality. We may never be able to measure it because of the newborn socialism’s effect on capitalism’s OCC (unless the American Empire manages to defeat China in WWIII, thus repeating its success against the USSR).”

      If Amerikan imperialism were to prevail over the rising Chinese imperialism, it would not resemble a repetition of the Cold War but rather a parallel to World War II, where the strongest imperialist power (Amerika) defeated the weaker imperialist power (Nazi Germany). Conversely, if the opposite were to occur, it would resemble the dynamics of World War I, with a rising imperialism (Yankee) surpassing the old, financially-oriented, and decadent imperialism (British).

      Nevertheless, regardless of the outcome, the working classes of the world would have little to gain from the exchange of one form of imperialism for another, capitalism and exploitation would persist, and despite the empty symbolic gestures of revisionists displaying hammer and sickles all over the place, wage slavery, commodity production, private property, crisis of overproduction, unequal exchange and so on still persist in China, as they do in every capitalist country.

      1. Your model implies that History always repeats itself, which is a contradiction in terms.

        The belief that the rise of China is a reboot of 1914-1918 is more difficult to sustain scientifically than the much more simple, beautiful, straightforward and evidence-based hypothesis that we’re simply entering a second Cold War (the period of 1992-2008 being the interregnum).

        The interpretation that China is the direct successor of the USSR is not a far-left delirium: it is simply the scientifically correct interpretation of History.

  2. Thank you for the overview. To his conclusion about refashioning Marx “as a pro-equality thinker who cared about trade union activity, equal opportunity, higher workers’ wages and the like,” I think he’d do well to read the Working Day chapter in Capital. Marx, as we know heralds this long and ongoing struggle.

  3. Even capitalists themselves are not fond of extreme inequality. How often do you hear discussions about excessive inequality in mainstream media? The reality is that capitalists recognize the need to mitigate the social contradictions of capitalism to keep their exploitative system going on. This is why social democrats and other reformist parties exist, they are not working-class parties! they always betray the proletariat and align with fascists during critical moments of class struggle! these bourgeois parties exist to co-opt the working class revolutionary spirit to ally with their oppressors. This is particularly evident in imperialist countries, where the ruling class bribes the working class with promises of consumerist lifestyles derived from the misery of the global South, shiny stuff for everyone! made by children from Africa. However, this phenomenon is not limited to imperialist countries; ruling classes in the global South also attempt to bribe part of their working classes with consumerist petty bourgeois lifestyles (see China as an example).

    The truth is that capitalists would prefer a version of capitalism with fewer contradictions: no climate change, no discrimination, no inequality, no poverty, no significant unemployment, and so on, stakeholder capitalism bullshit that the DAVOS fascists talk about. They would love an exploitative system that can continue indefinitely, no contradictions. However, they are unable to achieve this due to the systemic problems inherent in capitalism, not because they do not desire it. They have already made attempts with reformist bourgeois economics like Keynesianism and now with keynesianism 2.0 (MMT), both vulgar economics based on the false premise that we have non commodity money today, so the state can print money at will to guarantee ‘full employment’. The only way to fix capitalism is to overthrow it completely, to abolish commodity production, wage slavery, private ownership of the means of production, and so forth.

    In reality, reformists pose the greatest threat to the working classes. They are the equivalent of slave masters who bribe the slaves to keep slavery as long as the slave masters promise to give a filet mignon to the slaves from time to time.

  4. One very interesting aspect about these Iron Curtain intellectuals from the First Cold War is that they are very prone, not to say obsessed, with univeralism. It’s as if they don’t like to “waste time” with studying and analyzing concrete, smaller things, but want to demolish the whole thing with the biggest wrecking ball they can build.

    If one read Weber’s “How China scaped shock therapy”, you’ll see that, during the late 1970s, when Deng Xiaoping rose to power and wanted to hear opinions about how to proceed with the reforms of China, the CPC received a visit of some ten economists, most of them originally from the Warsaw Pact countries who fled to the West. They were the most formidable neoliberals, the most radicals. They did not know any concept of pragmatism, realism or even “third way”. Needless to say, the CPC listened, but didn’t see any use of their ideas.

    But if we observe today, we can see this universalist tradition of the Warsaw Pact is still with us: Janos Kornai, István Mészáros, Slavoj Zizek… and Branko Milanovic. My pet theory here is that they all had one thing in common: their unasailable hatred for the USSR. All of them, in their manner and strategy, had to elaborate a theory that had as its ultimate conclusion the USSR was an abortion of History; but since History is grandiose and it is hard to tackle socialism in this context, they had to tackle the problem as if it was one single thing, in a single and decisive blow, hence the tendency to universalism. That, and the objective condition of their countries, which were small and insignificant, so they had to use universalism in order to convince other nations to come to their “help”.

    Another factor must be that, since those countries didn’t have a true industrial revolution (all of their industry came from above, the USSR, without their aid), the Iron Curtain intelligentsia never had any industrial tradition; they never had to worry about applying their knowledge to technological or social progress (that role was reserved to the proletariat and the local communist party, as per the tradition of the USSR). It’s like the Iron Curtain intelligentsia “jumped” from the feudal-theological era directly to the socialist era, by teleportation; it’s as if their grandiose theories are moved by faith and not evidence.

    I think that’s the reason Branko Milanovic is obsessed with inequality. On the one hand, there’s the material base for his ideology, because that’s the subject that made him famous and prosperous; on the other hand, there’s this Iron Curtain tradition to find the idealist Being that explains all History with one single brushstroke. It also explains why he claims to have read and understood such a wide plethora of authors — which is, obviously, impossible for one single man to master in a lifetime.

    1. Agreed, but just to add that I came across an interesting chapter regarding US industrial expertise lent to the USSR in the 1920s in Behemoth, Joshua Freeman.

    2. VK, I think you are mistaken in placing Istvan Meszaros among the Universalist “Warsaw Pact” fakirs like Zizek. Meszaros was a true, not a fake marxist. Lenin himself defined the USSR’s mode of production as “state capitalism”. …Nor did Meszaros (or did his mentor, Lukacs) hate the USSR. I don’t think he even misunderstood Stalin’s role as historically necessary in leading the revolution’s forced-march towards industrialization (given its isolation after the betrayal of Western social democrat/fascists).

      Meszaros had no theory of the betrayal of the Russian revolution. But he was a humorousless stickler for correct terminology: Russia’s revolutionary, transitional mode of production, even in the industrialized USSR remained “state capitalism”, not “socialism”.

      Nevertheless Meszaros was a fexible historical materialist in support of actual revolutionary movements. For example, Meszaros learned as much from Chavez as Chavez from him. He supported Venezuela’s very problematic Bolivarian revolution. Do you? …Given your understanding of China (“socialist” or “state capitalist”) I think you would.

      1. I agree with you that Meszaros was a great philosopher, the good side of Iron Curtain universalism.

        But I have in mind his so-called “problem of temporality” in Marx — his only criticism on Marx. I think he’s mistaken on that: there is no temporality problem in Marx. The reason Meszaros thought there was is very public and straightforward (he wrote a whole session on Beyond Capital about this): the USSR and it’s descendants (including Cuba) were never socialist. He summarily disregards Chinese market socialism, fueling Marxism’s fame of Eurocentrism.

  5. The parallels between the work of some, such as Piketty, on inequality and the thinking of activists in movements for an increase in the minimum wage, a basic income and a job guarantee. To a large extent, they share many of the assumptions of the activists in these movements, and could be seen as a theoretical argument in their favor.

    These works show that there is a long-term trend towards inequality that was only temporarily reversed during a period in the middle of the twentieth century. As Zigedy argues, after the publication of Piketty’s book, the question is not whether inequality increased, but why it slowed or reversed at mid-century.

    As is typical of simple economists, the alleged “cause” of this problem is tautological: when the increase in wealth of the owners of capital exceeds the increase in wealth of society as a whole, inequality increases. This profound observation is represented in the idiotic equation :

    r > g
    Where r is the rate of return on capital and g is the growth rate of the national economy as a whole. This equation, which purports to explain some hidden relationship in the structure of social relations, really only tells us that when the increase in the mass of wealth accruing to the capitalist exceeds the increase in the mass of wealth accruing to society as a whole, wealth will be concentrated in the hands of capitalists – something every sensible reader knew even before opening the book.
    So, what is the explanation for hundreds of years of secular increase in the concentration of wealth in the hands of a few?

    According to some, the distribution of wealth has always been political, and cannot be reduced to economic mechanisms. The slowdown in inequality (roughly between the wars) and its acceleration after 1980 (roughly “neoliberalism”) are the result of war and the policies adopted to deal with it. So, the argument goes, there is no economic mechanism for what he calls a long-standing secular trend towards wealth inequality.

    -We are therefore faced with two contradictory assertions: firstly, that rising inequality is driven by political forces; secondly, that the more free markets depend on political forces, the more inequality increases. The state itself is the source of inequality, but the absence of state intervention is the condition for the expansion of inequality,

  6. Capitalism in the 21st Century: Through the Prism of Value (London: Pluto Press, 2023) Is there a French translation? Lu interviews Gianni Del Panta -Guglielmo Carchedi and Michael Roberts-

  7. “The tendency of the profit rate to fall must reduce inequality because capitalists (together with landlords who are treated just as a subgroup of capitalists) are the richest class. Clearly, if the top class’s incomes do not rise, or even decline, we may expect an improvement in distribution. This may be true even if there is an increased concentration of capitalists’ incomes and some capitalists become very rich while others go bankrupt and join workers.”

    The first sentence is the conclusion to be asserted, i.e., the topic sentence.

    The second sentence however does not seem to me to be correct even in its own terms, as secular stagnation, a relatively static level of production (absent profitability, investment is relatively stagnant as well) will indeed lower the magnitude of incomes and properties for the bourgeoisie. But not only can population growth not be sustained by the unpropertied, but actual physical production may be increasingly inadequate to maintain the living standards of the lower levels. Indeed, population may decline. I do not see how this could possibly be construed as an “improvement in distribution.” [The tacit assumption is that population is under individual control and like consumer sovereignty is not to be questioned.] I think it is historically well attested that such a state of affairs is possible. I don’t see how this makes any sense at all, even in his own terms.

    The third sentence views an increase in the concentration of income (and wealth too?) in a fraction of the old bourgeoisie and the proletarianization of losing members of that fraction of society is somehow also read as an “improvement” in distribution! The greater ability of billionaires to control media and politics or simply to jack up real estate prices or divert material resources to luxury production does not strike me as an improvement. The only way this seems to me to be true is if the rise of wage rates is so rapid that it raises the median wage *more* than the relative rise in capitalists’ income! This seems like a much more specific yet more dubious claim than the argument the resources devoted to machinery, power and raw materials must in the end rise faster than the resources devoted to acquiring labor precisely because it is the investment that permits the relative surplus value—which becomes ever more important the more productive an economy is, I think—to rise. Again, I don’t see how Milanovic is even following his own logic here, much less addressing historical experience in general rather than an undefined hypothetical. Why for that matter does capitalism have such a powerful, historically attested, tendency to accumulate capital? Because raising the organic composition of capital raises the rate of relative surplus value, and potentially the rate of profits, how much depending on the individual capitalist’s particular situation, which seems like an answer to me, but Milanovic rejects this as “indeterminate?”

    And there are two other things I don’t understand. First, if Milanovic doesn’t accept that the law of the tendency of the rate of profit to tall is “determinate,” what is Milanovic’s explanation of business cycles? The issue is not a clockwork precision, which obviously doesn’t exist, but the problem of why there is *any* periodicity. That’s why I think so much of economics still flirts with proving that crises are illusory. And the schools that argue crises are due to, essentially, Bad Actors (the favorite is government but banks/financiers are also popular) or Acts of God (the ultimate Bad Actor?) can’t explain the rough periodicity either, so far as I know. As far as secular declines in profit rates are concerned, the devlopment of profuctive forces has in the very long run advanced the material well-being of humanity as a whole, but the argument it has not also advanced inequality seems to me to be very shaky. Why is this if the law of the tendency of the rate of profit to fall is “indeterminate?”

    The second issue may stem from Milanovic essentially denying things like a general glut of commodities can truly occur? So far as I know history, crises have been the breeding ground of inequality. Those who managed to keep some money in a crisis acquire property as knockdown prices. Speculative bubbles impoverished many but the lucky few who sold in time were permanently richer. Those who managed to hang onto property in, for example, frontier land investments or stocks despite the vicissitudes of crises got rich and those who needed cash for family expenses, didn’t. Over a lifetime, unemployment is like major illness, and the family finances of the unpropertied are permanently retarded. When the crisis achieves the destruction (literal or financial) of capital sufficient to restore profitability, these advantages and disadvantages are permanent and multiplied.

    Not sure that Milanovic should be taken seriously at all. The notion that the rich are homoploutia in the flesh in particular strikes me more as sycophancy than a real thing.

  8. Here’s the problem:
    This statement:

    Capitalism
    ???
    communism

    Practically translates into this statement:

    Capitalism
    Wages fall to zero
    communism

    And this statement:

    Capitalism (Jobs, jobs, jobs!)
    100% unemployment
    communism

    It’s very easy to understand how we get to communism when capitalism does all the dirty work. It’s that middle part, when wages fall to zero and unemployment reaches 100%, that bothers people, I guess. People have a really hard time imagining a future in which nobody has a job or a salary.

    Right. If we can’t find a way to bring our own wages down to zero, capital can do it for us.

    The problem is that this is also the definition of communism. People know, of course, that under communism, nobody has a job or a wage, but they just can’t see how to do it without big problems. So they try to find a way to get to communism so that everyone still has a job and good wages. They keep coming up against this brick wall and become discouraged.

    No need to get discouraged: capitalism will take all your jobs and wages and leave you with nothing.

    1. This is a common misconception that we inherited from the political debate between the Bolsheviks and the Social-Democrats: the “mechanicists”/”determinists” vs. “Western Marxists”.

      But when you read and understand what Marx actually published, it all becomes very clear: Communism is the only POSITIVE SOLUTION to capital(ism). That means that, if humanity is to continue History from the objective conditions of capitalism, the solution will have to be, logically, Communism.

      But not every solution is positive. Marx was very aware that History was neither obligatory to human existence (the many tribes without History) nor did it needed to end positively (the many historical societies that were vanquished by conquest or natural cataclysms).

      So, the answer is: Communism is both inevitable and optative. If humanity solves capitalism positively, Marx demonstrated logically that it will, in it’s mathematical limit, be a model that approaches Communism. Or, alternatively, humanity may solve capitalism negatively, which may mean anything between going back to the proverbial Stone Age to outward extinction of the human species.

      1. For hundreds of thousands of years, man has lived in communities, the “genos” the principal stock.
        “Marshall Shalin” American anthropologist, specialist in the economy of primitive and prehistoric societies. -Stone Age age of abundance – abundance of everything, human relationships of love of affects of enjoyment of life and the given all of human production and reproduction.
        Lewis H. Morgan, founder of modern anthropology, also testified to this, and Marx was aware of some of his work.
        -Exchange value – exploded these imperfect, localized communities.
        By becoming a world, capitalism accomplishes the becoming of the universal human community.
        Of course, in bourgeois ideals, prehistory represents a shaggy man emerging from a damp, smoky cave with a 15kg club.
        Until we rid the planet of this mode of production for profit….

      2. I broadly agree with this comment, but would like to add a few caveats.
        It’s up to us to be relatively precise, for example between societies and communities.
        The first peoples have no History, since they have no exchange value, even if they sometimes barter (the eternal return of the same).
        This is where the subjective comes in, evoking the age-old concepts of alienation and reification (the proletarian is a failed bourgeois).
        The ultimate referent of “German ideology”, man is only the how, of what he produces and reproduces… so he can start to think. As for the Mad Max world of profit, it’s already in the making, so be patient.

  9. It is said the law of TRPF is “both the explanation of regular and recurring cycles of crises (booms and slumps) and also a secular law indicating the ultimate failure of capitalist production to develop the productive forces for humanity.” It definitely explains cycles. The rate falls, a crisis hits. Capital values die in the crisis, setting the scene for a repeat of profitable investments, a falling rate again, and the next crisis.

    But there is a problem with the law as the explanation of the ultimate failure. Namely, what is the tipping point? The cycle repeats and repeats, then one time it cannot? Relying on “the masses finally take it no more” is hardly firm ground.

    Marx suggested, “At a certain stage of development, the material productive forces of society come into conflict with the existing relations of production… From forms of development of the productive forces these relations turn into their fetters. Then begins an era of social revolution.” Marx did not connect this change with the law of TRPF. In his day he could not know what the certain stage of development would be. Now we know: it has been in action since the mid-1970s in the U.S. See The Hollow Colossus.

    1. It seems to me Marx did not conceive a theory, not even the law of the tendency of the rate of profit to fall, then use it as a key to interpret current events and to make forecasts. It seems to me that Marx learned his politics from real movements, then used his previously acquired knowledge of philosophy to generalize the experiences of others. (Experience keeps a harsh school, therefore true wisdom is learning from *others’ hard-won lessons,* I think.) And he earnestly and industriously acquired true expertise in political economy to make sure the theory, the basic understanding as presented after due reflection on variegated reality in an intelligible form permitting the correct analysis of where we are and where we are going and some of the things we must do if we want to get there, was both valid and useful as possible.

      I think that’s why Marx’s theories did not explicitly articulate the role of labor, either as a political movement in a bourgeois democracy or as a worldwide trade union movement in revolution. He took his notion of the dictatorship of proletariat from the real life models of the Great French Revolution and the Paris Commune. Being something of a lacuna, the real unclosed part of his system (contra the peculiar von Boehm-Bawerk) that I think was why social democracy and Communism can both claim descent from Marx. It’s vaguely analogous I suppose to how Marx and Engels on the one hand can be descendants of the Enlightenment yet in their own way so too are, say, Bentham and Constant. It is a commonplace tactic of Marx-kritik to verbally acknowledge that Marx was a good describer of the old unreformed capitalism but (wink, wink) that’s all changed now. It’s an old impressionist story, from Bernstein on.

      To my eyes, though, Marx has always been one of the few writers on political economy who has openly predicted the inevitability of the business cycle *and* the inevitability of general crises. One of those general crises underlay the outbreak of WWI, the Great War as it was called. And it was Marx who openly predicted immiseration of the proletariat. I think that if you look at the whole world system of capitalism/imperialism, this thesis has been validated. I even think that the inability of the walled gardens of the great powers of imperialism to abolish poverty in their illusory national paradise is yet another confirmation of Marx. It’s economics that seems to me wrong, not Marx. But to me this is another way of saying the law of the tendency of the rate of profit to fall has a secular expression. The terrifying and horrifying epochal breakdowns of the imperialist systems in war are the political consequences of national bourgeoisies failing to manage the impossible contradictions of a system that is getting crazier and crazier. The increasing nuttiness is the secular trend in the fundamental law inexorably working itself out.

      What Marx did not predict is, fascism. I think the existence of fascism has posed a challenge to social democracy that for a century now social democracy has failed to meet, when it even tried. The thing is, fascism is an example of the law where cheapening labor power to the point where the proletariat cannot reproduce itself has become a fundamental strategy. The tiny grain of “rationality” in this is, it is supposed to be some *other* bourgeoisie’s proletariat (and rival bourgeoisie too if possible, but practically usually open to a deal, right?) that does the non-reproducing! The fact that this is more blood simple, than genuinely rational, that it’s a strategy for common ruin forgets, Paradise Lost, better to rule in Hell…

      And by the way I strongly suspect that the way the law attributes cheapening the constant capital—-which includes natural resources in general, aka the biosphere—is an element leading to degradation of the material prerequisites for human life in general. The Earth will survive us. Probably half of all life is bacteria anyway and “we” aren’t about to kill them off! To me it seems plausible that a capitalist system, where the value of constant capital must equal, ultimately the labor power it takes to appropriate the gifts of nature, whether directly or in the manufacture of physical capital used, forbids any rational valuation of the utility of the environment for humanity at large. And I suspect this “discounting” problem* is insoluble even given schemes for trying to assign fictitious property rights to humanity or the future or even for God’s sake nature itself.

      The thing is, from what I can tell of your interventions, you are looking for social democracy, bourgeois democracy plus. Sorry, don’t think that will work. The first three paragraphs of this comment, are meant to make clear why your perspective, insofar as I can make it out, is I think wrong. Sorry to be tedious going over some basics but I think rejecting the law is rejecting a key principle of the scientific analysis. And getting the basics wrong leads you wrong, no matter how boring it is to read the ABC again.

      *The phrase discounting problem may or may not be widespread in the economics literature. I confess I found it in a brief discussion by Kim Stanley Robinson in his novel The Ministry of the Future. But Robinson, although widely considered a leftist, always struck me more as a mildly reformist social democrat.

  10. Another great piece…One comment re political economics: Profits tend to drop in competitive markets. When the largest owners of capital exert power over government policy (inevitable), markets are likely to become less competitive and more dominated by monopolies that can raise prices and extract more rent. Years of lack of anti-trust enforcement is a big issue in the US – may be shifting some. Higher monopoly rents hurt low-income people the most – and push down their relative wealth. Govt policies – eg, US gov failure to negotiate effectively with the medical industrial complex/Big Pharma – expand flow of $$ from consumers/taxpayers to powerful business interests and aggregations of capital. Need to remember the politics in econ analysis. Just sayin.

  11. In the end the overthrow of capitalism is a conscious political act by workers driven by the emergence of intolerable material conditions. The primary driver being the crisis of profitability which has to be understood in the round. It’s not about how low the rate of profit falls, but the fact that, were workers to defend themselves from the counter crisis measures needed to restore the rate, profitability would collapse and with it the heartbeat of capitalism. On top of this we we have war, AI and global heating.

    I am proud to have helped initiate and organize a large contingent from my City to the anti Zionist march in London. This is a momentous spontaneous international movement fuelled by anger and disgust, which could lay the basis for a more durable and conscious movement to prevent world war three.

Leave a comment

This site uses Akismet to reduce spam. Learn how your comment data is processed.